photo of Immanuel Kant
Photo Credit: WikiMedia Commons

200 Inspiring Quotes by Immanuel Kant

Welcome to our collection of quotes (with shareable picture quotes) by Immanuel Kant. We hope you enjoy pondering them and that you will share them widely.

Wikipedia Summary for Immanuel Kant

Immanuel Kant (UK: , US: ; German: [ɪˈmaːnu̯eːl ˈkant, -nu̯ɛl -]; 22 April 1724 – 12 February 1804) was a German philosopher and one of the central Enlightenment thinkers. Kant's comprehensive and systematic works in epistemology, metaphysics, ethics, and aesthetics have made him one of the most influential figures in modern Western philosophy.

In his doctrine of transcendental idealism, Kant argued that space and time are mere "forms of intuition" which structure all experience, and therefore that while "things-in-themselves" exist and contribute to experience, they are nonetheless distinct from the objects of experience. From this it follows that the objects of experience are mere "appearances", and that the nature of things as they are in themselves is consequently unknowable to us. In an attempt to counter the skepticism he found in the writings of philosopher David Hume, he wrote the Critique of Pure Reason (1781/1787), one of his most well-known works. In it, he developed his theory of experience to answer the question of whether synthetic a priori knowledge is possible, which would in turn make it possible to determine the limits of metaphysical inquiry. Kant drew a parallel to the Copernican revolution in his proposal that the objects of the senses must conform to our spatial and temporal forms of intuition, and that we can consequently have a priori cognition of the objects of the senses.

Kant believed that reason is also the source of morality, and that aesthetics arise from a faculty of disinterested judgment. Kant's views continue to have a major influence on contemporary philosophy, especially the fields of epistemology, ethics, political theory, and post-modern aesthetics. He attempted to explain the relationship between reason and human experience and to move beyond what he believed to be the failures of traditional philosophy and metaphysics. He wanted to put an end to what he saw as an era of futile and speculative theories of human experience, while resisting the skepticism of thinkers such as Hume. He regarded himself as showing the way past the impasse between rationalists and empiricists, and is widely held to have synthesized both traditions in his thought.

Kant was an exponent of the idea that perpetual peace could be secured through universal democracy and international cooperation, and that perhaps this could be the culminating stage of world history. The nature of Kant's religious views continues to be the subject of scholarly dispute, with viewpoints ranging from the impression that he shifted from an early defense of an ontological argument for the existence of God to a principled agnosticism, to more critical treatments epitomized by Schopenhauer, who criticized the imperative form of Kantian ethics as "theological morals" and the "Mosaic Decalogue in disguise", and Nietzsche, who claimed that Kant had "theologian blood" and was merely a sophisticated apologist for traditional Christian faith. Beyond his religious views, Kant has also been criticized for the racism presented in some of his lesser-known papers, such as "On the Use of Teleological Principles in Philosophy" and "On the Different Races of Man". Although he was a proponent of scientific racism for much of his career, Kant's views on race changed significantly in the last decade of his life, and he ultimately rejected racial hierarchies and European colonialism in Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch (1795), though still considering Europeans as "civilized" to the exception of others.

Kant published other important works on ethics, religion, law, aesthetics, astronomy, and history during his lifetime. These include the Universal Natural History (1755), the Critique of Practical Reason (1788), the Critique of Judgment (1790), Religion within the Bounds of Bare Reason (1793), and the Metaphysics of Morals (1797).

--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant

--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant

--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant

--Immanuel Kant



--Immanuel Kant

--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant

Longer Version:

Ours is an age of criticism, to which everything must be subjected. The sacredness of religion, and the authority of legislation, are by many regarded as grounds for exemption from the examination by this tribunal, But, if they are exempted, and cannot lay claim to sincere respect, which reason accords only to that which has stood the test of a free and public examination.


--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant

--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant

--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant

--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant

--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant

--Immanuel Kant

--Immanuel Kant

--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant

Longer Version:

Nature does nothing in vain, and in the use of means to her goals she is not prodigal. Her giving to man reason and the freedom of the will which depends upon it is clear indication of her purpose. Man accordingly was not to be guided by instinct, not nurtured and instructed with ready-made knowledge; rather, he should bring forth everything out of his own resources.


--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant

--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant

Longer Version:

All our knowledge begins with the senses, proceeds then to the understanding, and ends with reason. There is nothing higher than reason.


--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant

--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant
--Immanuel Kant

Cite this page:

APA Style Citation:

MLA Style Citation:

Link Back to Us: (preferred, thank you!)

Thank you for citing us - and thank you for sharing our quotes and quotepics - spread the joy - we appreciate it!


We wish you a perfect day!